Grammatical Framework for the working Mathematician

23 minute read

Introduction

For this inaugural blog-post, I will introduce Grammatical Framework (GF) through an extended example targeted at a general audience familiar with logic, functional programming, or mathematics. GF is a powerful tool for specifying grammars. A grammar specification in GF is actually an abstract syntax. With an abstract syntax specified, one can then define various linearization rules which compositionally evaluate to strings. An Abstract Syntax Tree (AST) may then be linearized to various strings admitted by different concrete syntaxes. Conversely, given a string admitted by the language being defined, GF’s powerful parser will generate all the ASTs which linearize to that tree.

Focus of this tutorial

We introduce this subject assuming no familiarity with GF, but a general mathematical and programming maturity. While GF is certainly geared to applications in domain specific machine translation, this writing will hopefully make evident that learning about GF, even without the intention of using it for its intended application, is a useful exercise in abstractly understanding syntax and its importance in just about any domain.

A working high-level introduction of Grammatical Framework emphasizing both theoretical and practical elements of GF, as well as their interplay. Specific things covered will be

  • Historical developments leading to the creation and discovery of the GF formalism
  • The difference between Abstract and Concrete Syntax, and the linearization and parsing functions between these two categories
  • The basic judgments :
    • Abstract : cat, fun
    • Concrete : lincat, lin
    • Auxiliary : oper, param
  • A library for building natural language applications with GF
    • The Resource Grammar Library (RGL)
    • A way of interfacing GF with Haskell and transforming ASTs externally
    • The Portable Grammar Format (PGF)
  • Module System and directory structure
  • A brief comparison with other tools like BNFC

These topics will be understood via a simple example of an expression language, Arith, which will serve as a case study for understanding the many robust, theoretical topics mentioned above - indeed, mathematics is best understood and learned through examples. Possible exercises will be interspersed throughout, but per usual, the best exercises are the reader’s own ideas, questions, and contentions which may arise while reading through this.

Theoretical Overview

What is a GF grammar ?

[TODO : update with latex]

Consider a language L, for now given a single linear presentation C^L_0, where AST_L String_L0 denote the sets GF ASTs and Strings in the languages generated by the rules of L’s abstract syntax and L0s compositional representation.

Parse : String -> {AST} Linearize : AST -> String

with the important property that given a string s,

forall x in (Parse s), Linearize x == s

And given an AST a, we can Parse . Linearize a belongs to {AST}

Now we should explore why the linearizations are interesting. In part, this is because they have arisen from the role of grammars have played in the intersection and interaction between computer science and linguistics at least since Chomsky in the 50s, and they have different understandings and utilities in the respective disciplines. These two discplines converge in GF, which allows us to talk about natural languages (NLs) from programming languages (PLs) perspective. GF captures languages more expressive than Chomsky’s Context Free Grammars (CFGs) but is still decideable with parsing in (cubic?) polynomial time, which means it still is quite domain specific and leaves a lot to be desired as far as turing complete languages or those capable of general recursion are concerned.

We can should note that computa

given a string s , perhaps a phrase map Linearize (Parse s)

is understood as the set of translations of a phrase of one language to possibly grammatical phrases in the other languages connected by a mutual abstract syntax. So we could denote these L^English, L^Bantu, L^Swedish for L^Englsih_American vs L^Englsih_English or L^Bantu_i with i being any one of the Bantu languages a hypothetical set of linguists and grammar writers may want to implement, on a given fragment of abstract syntax, with various domain applications, as determined by L, in mind.

One could also further elaborate these L^English_0 L^English_1 to varying degrees of granularity, like L^English_Chomsky L^English_Partee because Chomsky may something like “I was stoked” and Partee may only say something analogous “I was really excited” or whatever the individual nuances come with how speakers say what they mean with different surface syntax, and also

L_0 < L_1 -> L_English_0 < L_English_1

But this would be similair to a set of expressions translateable between programming languages, like Logic^English, Logic^Latex, Logic^Agda, Logic^Coq, etc

where one could extend the

Logic_Core^English Logic_Extended^English

whereas in the PL domain

Logic_Core^Agda Logic_Extended^Agda may collapse at certain points, but also in some ways extend beyond our Languages capacities (we can make machine code only machines can understand, not us)

or Mathematics = Logic + domain specific Mathematics^English Mathematics^Agda

where we could have further refinements, via, for instance, the module system, the concrete and linear designs like

Mathematics^English iI – Something about

The Functor (in the module sense familiar to ML programmers)

break down to different classifications of

– Something about

The Functor (in the module sense familiar to ML programmers)

break down to different classifications of

The indexes here, while seemingly arbitrary,

One could also further elaborate these L^English_0 L^English_1 to varying degrees of granularity, like L^English_Chomsky L^English_Partee

because Chomsky may something like “I was stoked” and Partee may only say something analogous “I was really excited” or whatever the individual nuances come with how speakers say what they mean with different surface syntax, and also

Given a set of categories, we define the functions \phi : (c_1, …, c_n) -> c_t over the categories which will serve as the constructors of our ASTs. The categories and functions are denoted in GF with the cat and fun judgment.

Some preliminary observations and considerations

There are many ways to skin a cat. While in some sense GF offers the user a limited palette with which to paint, she nonetheless has quite a bit of flexibility in her decision making when designing a GF grammar for a specific domain or application. These decisions are not binary, but rest in the spectrum of of considerations varying between :

  • immediate usability and long term sustainability
  • prototyping and production readiness
  • dependency on external resources liable to change
  • research or application oriented
  • sensitivity and vulnerability to errors
  • scalability and maintainability

Many answers to where on the spectrum a Grammar lies will only become clear a posteriori to code being written, which often contradicts prior decisions which had been made and requires significant efforts to refactor. General best practices that apply to all programming languages, like effective use of modularity, can and should be applied by the GF programmer out of the box, whereas the strong type system also promotes a degree of rigidity with which the programmer is forced to stay in a certain safety boundary. Nonetheless, a grammar is in some sense a really large program, which brings a whole series of difficulties.

When designing a GF grammar for a given application, the most immediate question that will come to mind is separation of concerns as regards the spectrum of

[Abstract <-> Concrete] syntax

Have your cake and eat it ?

A grammar for basic arithmetic

Judgments

A central contribution of Per Martin-Löf in the development of type theory was the recognition of the centrality of judgments in logic. Many mathematicians aren’t familiar with the spectrum of judgments available, and merely believe they are concerned with the notion of truth, namely the truth of a mathematical proposition or theorem. There are many judgments one can make which most mathematicians aren’t aware of or at least never mention. These include, for instance,

  • \(A\) is a proposition
  • \(A\) is possible
  • \(A\) is probable

These judgments are understood not in the object language in which we state our propositions, possibilities, or probabilities, but as assertions in the metalanguage which require evidence for us to know and believe them. Most mathematicians may reach for their wallets if I come in and give a talk saying it is possible that the Riemann Hypothesis is true, partially because they already know that, and partially because it doesn’t seem particularly interesting to say that something is possible, in the same way that a physicist may flinch if you say alchemy is possible. Most mathematicians, however, would agree that \(P = NP\) is possible but isn’t probable.

For the logician these judgments may well be interesting because their may be logics in which the discussion of possibility or probability is even more interesting than the discussion of truth. And for the type theorist, interested in designing and building programming languages over many various logics, these judgments become a prime focus. The role of the type-checker in a programming language is to present evidence for, or decide the validity of the judgments. The four main judgments of type theory are :

  • \(T\) is a type
  • \(T\) and \(T'\) are equal types
  • \(t\) is a term of type \(T\)
  • \(t\) and \(t'\) are equal terms of type \(T\)

We succinctly present these in a mathematical notation where Frege’s turnstile, \(\vdash\), denotes a judgment :

\[\vdash T \; {\rm type}\] \[\vdash T = T'\] \[\vdash t {:} T\] \[\vdash t = t' {:} T\]

These judgments become much more interesting when we add the ability for them to be interpreted in a some context with judgment hypotheses. Given a series of judgments \(J_1,...,J_n\), denoted \(\Gamma\), where \(J_i\) can depend on previously listed \(J's\), we can make judgment \(J\) under the hypotheses, e.g. \(J_1,...,J_n \vdash J\). Often these hypotheses \(J_i\), alternatively called antecedents, denote variables which may occur freely in the consequent judgment \(J\). For instance, the antecedent, \(x {:} \R\) occurs freely in the syntactic expression \(\sin x\), a which is given meaning in the judgment \(\vdash \sin x {:} \R\). We write our hypothetical judgement as follows :

\[x {:} \R \vdash \sin x {:} \R\]

One reason why hypothetical judgments are so interesting is we can devise rules which allow us to translate from the metalanguage to the object language using lambda expressions. These play the role of a function in mathematics and implication in logic. This comes out in the following introduction rule :

\[\frac{\Gamma, x {:} A \vdash b {:} B} {\Gamma \vdash \lambda x. b {:} A \rightarrow B}\]

Using this rule, we now see a typical judgment, typical in a field like from real analysis,

\[\vdash \lambda x. \sin x {:} \R \rightarrow \R\]

Equality :

Mathematicians denote this judgement

\[\begin{align} f {:} \R &\rightarrow \R\\ x &\mapsto \sin ( x ) \end{align}\]

Abstract Judgments

The core syntax of GF is quite simple. The abstract syntax specification, denoted mathematically above as _, and in GF as Arith.gf is given by :

abstract Arith = {
...
}

Note : All GF files end with the .gf file extension. More detailed information about abstract, concrete, modules, etc. relevant for GF is specified internal to a *.gf file

The abstract specification is simple, and reveals GF’s power and elegance. The two primary abstract judgments are :

  1. cat : denoting a syntactic category
  2. fun : denoting a n-ary function over categories. This is essentially a labeled context-free rewrite rule with (non-)terminal string information suppressed

Additional Judgments: While there are more advanced abstract judgments, for instance def allows one to incorporate semantic information, discussion of these will be deferred to other resources.

These judgments have different interpretations in the natural and formal language settings. Let’s see the spine of the Arith language, where we merely want to be able to write expressions like ( 3 + 4 ) * 5 in a myriad of concrete syntaxes.

cat Exp ; 

fun
  Add  : Exp -> Exp -> Exp ;
  Mul  : Exp -> Exp -> Exp ;
  EInt : Int -> Exp ;

To represent this abstractly, we merely have two binary operators, labeled Add and Mul, whose intended interpretation is just the operator names, and the EInt function which coerces a predefined Int, natively supported numerical strings "0","1","2",... into arithmetic expressions. We can now generate our first abstract syntax tree, corresponding to the above expression, Mul (Add (EInt 3) (EInt 4)) (EInt 5), more readable perhaps with the tree structure expanded :

Mul 
  Add 
    EInt 3
    EInt 4 
  EInt 5

The trees nodes are just the function names, and the leaves, while denoted above as numbers, are actually function names for the built-in numeric strings which happen to be linearized to the same piece of syntax, i.e. linearize 3 == 3, where the left-hand 3 has type Int and the right-hand 3 has type Str.

Builtin Categories : GF has support for very few, but important categories. These are Int, Float, and String. It is my contention and that adding user defined builtin categories would greatly ease the burden of work for people interested in using GF to model programming languages, because String makes the grammars notoriously ambiguous.

In computer science terms, to judge Foo to be a given category cat Foo; corresponds to the definition of a given Algebraic Datatypes (ADTs) in Haskell, or inductive definitions in Agda, whereas the function judgments fun correspond to the various constructors. These connections become explicit in the PGF embedding of GF into Haskell, but examining the Haskell code below makes one suspect their is some equivalence lurking in the corner:

data Exp = Add Exp Exp | Mul Exp Exp | EInt Int

In linguistics we can interpret the judgments via alternatively simple and standard examples:

  1. cat : these could be syntactic categories like Common Nouns CN, Noun Phrases NP , and determiners Det
  2. fun : give us ways of combining words or phrases into more complex syntactic units

For instance, if

fun 
  Car_CN  : CN ;
  The_Det : Det ;
  DetCN   : Det -> CN -> NP ;

Then one can form a tree DetCN The_Det Car_CN which should linearize to "the car" in English, bilen in Swedish, and imoto in Zulu once we have implemented concrete syntax linearizations for these respective languages, which we will now do.

While there was an equivalence suggested Haskell ADTs should be careful not to treat these as the same as the GF judgments. Indeed, the linguistic interpretation breaks this analogy, because linguistic categories aren’t stable mathematical objects in the sense that they evolved and changed during the evolution of language, and will continue to do so. Since GF is primarily concerned with parsing and linearization of languages, the full power of inductive definitions in Agda, for instance, doesn’t seem like a particularly natural space to study and model natural language phenomena.

Arith.gf

Below we recapitulate, for completeness, the whole Arith.gf file with all the pieces from above glued together, which, the reader should start to play with.

abstract Arith = {

flags startcat = Exp ;

-- a judgement which says "Exp is a category"
cat
  Exp ;

fun
  Add  : Exp -> Exp -> Exp ; -- "+"
  Mul  : Exp -> Exp -> Exp ; -- "*"
  EInt : Int -> Exp ; -- "33"

}

The astute reader will recognize some code which has not yet been described. The comments, delegated with --, can have their own lines or be given at the end of a piece of code. It is good practice to give example linearizations as comments in the abstract syntax file, so that it can be read in a stand-alone way.

The flags startcat = Exp ; line is not a judgment, but piece of metadata for the compiler so that it knows, when generating random ASTs, to include a function at the root of the AST with codomain Exp. If I hadn’t included flags startcat = *some cat* , and ran gr in the gf shell, we would get the following error, which can be incredibly confusing but simple bug to fix if you know what to look for!

Category S is not in scope
CallStack (from HasCallStack):
  error, called at src/compiler/GF/Command/Commands.hs:881:38 in gf-3.10.4-BNI84g7Cbh1LvYlghrRUOG:GF.Command.Commands

Concrete Judgments

We now append our abstract syntax GF file Arith.gf with our first concrete GF syntax, some pigdin English way of saying our same expression above, namely the product of the sum of 3 and 4 and 5. Note that Mul and Add both being binary operators preclude this reading : product of (the sum of 3 and 4 and 5) in GF, despite the fact that it seems the more natural English interpretation and it doesn’t admit a proper semantic reading.

Reflecting the tree around the Mul root, Mul (EInt 5) (Add (EInt 3) (EInt 4)), we get a reading where the ‘natural interpretation’ matches the actual syntax :the product of 5 and the sum of 3 and 4. Let’s look at the concrete syntax which allow us to simply specify the linearization rules corresponding to the above fun function judgments.

Our concrete syntax header says that ArithEng1 is constrained by the fact that the concrete syntaxes must share the same prefix with the abstract syntax, and extend it with one or more characters, i.e. Arith+.gf.

concrete ArithEng1 of Arith = {
...
}

We now introduce the two concrete syntax judgments which compliment those above, namely :

  • cat is dual to lincat
  • fun is dual to lin

Here is the first pass at an English linearization :

lincat
  Exp = Str ;

lin
  Add e1 e2 = "the sum of" ++ e1 ++ "and" ++ e2 ;
  Mul e1 e2 = "the product of" ++ e1 ++ "and" ++ e2 ;
  EInt i = i.s ;

The lincat judgement says that Exp category is given a linearization type Str, which means that any expression is just evaluated to a string. There are more expressive linearization types, records and tables, or products and coproducts in the mathematician’s lingo. For instance, EInt i = i.s that we project the s field from the integer i (records are indexed by numbers but rather by names in PLs). We defer a more extended discussion of linearization types for later examples where they are not just useful but necessary, producing grammars more expressive than CFGs called Parallel Multiple Context Free Grammars (PMCFGs).

The linearization of the Add function takes two arguments, e1 and e2 which must necessarily evaluate to strings, and produces a string. Strings in GF are denoted with double quotes "my string" and concatenation with ++. This resulting string, "the sum of" ++ e1 ++ "and" ++ e2 is the concatenation of "the sum of", the evaluated string e1, "and", and the string of a linearized e2. The linearization of EInt is almost an identity function, except that the primitive Integer’s are strings embedded in a record for scalability purposes.

Here is the relationship between fun and lin from a slightly higher vantage point. Given a fun judgement

\[f {:} C_0 \rightarrow C_1 \rightarrow ... \rightarrow C_n\]

in the abstract file, the GF user provides a corresponding lin judgement of the form

\[f \: c_0 \: c_1 \: ... \: c_n \: {=} \: t_0 \: \texttt{++} \: t_1 \: \texttt{++} \: ... \: \texttt{++} \: t_m\]

in the concrete file. Each \(c_i\) must have the linearization type given in the lincat of \(C_i\) , e.g. if lincat C_i = T ; then c_i : T.

We step through the example above to see how the linearization recursively evaluates, noting that this may not be the actual reduction order GF internally performs. The relation ->* informally used but not defined here expresses the step function after zero or more steps of evaluating an expression. This is the reflexive transitive closure of the single step relation -> familiar in operational semantics.

linearize (Mul (Add (EInt 3) (EInt 4)) (EInt 5))
->* "the product of" ++ linearize (Add (EInt 3) (EInt 4)) ++ "and" ++ linearize (EInt 5)
->* "the product of" ++ ("the sum of" ++ (EInt 3) ++ (EInt 4)) ++ "and" ++ ({ s = "5"} . s)
->* "the product of" ++ ("the sum of" ++ ({ s = "3"} . s) ++ ({ s = "4"} . s)) ++ "and" ++ "5"
->* "the product of" ++ ("the sum of" ++ "3" ++ "and" ++ "4") ++ "and" ++ "5"
->* "the product of" ++ ("the sum of" ++ "3" ++ "and" ++ "4") ++ "and" ++ "5"
->* "the product of the sum of 3 and 4 and 5"

The PMCFG class of languages is still quite tame when compared with, for instance, Turing complete languages. Thus, the abstract and concrete coupling tight, the evaluation is quite simple, and the programs tend to write themselves once the correct types are chosen. This is not to say GF programming is easier than in other languages, because often there are unforeseen constraints that the programmer must get used to, limiting the palette available when writing code. These constraints allow for fast parsing, but greatly limit the types of programs one often thinks of writing. We touch upon this in a previous section.

Now that the basics of GF have been described, we will augment our grammar so that it becomes slightly more interesting, introduce a second concrete syntax, and show how to run these in the GF shell in order to translate between our two languages.

The GF Shell

So now that we have a GF abstract and concrete syntax pair, one needs to test the grammars.

Once GF is installed, one can open both the abstract and concrete with the gf shell command applied to the concrete syntax, assuming the abstract syntax is in the same directory :

$ gf ArithEng1.gf

I’ll forego describing many important details and commands, please refer to the official shell reference and Inari Listenmaa’s post on tips and gotchas for a more nuanced take than I give here.

The ls of the gf repl is gr. What does gr do? Lets try it, as well as ask gf what it does:

Arith> gr 
Add (EInt 999) (Mul (Add (EInt 999) (EInt 999)) (EInt 999))

0 msec
Arith> help gr
gr, generate_random
generate random trees in the current abstract syntax

We see that the tree generated isn’t random - 999 is used exclusively, and obviously if the trees were actually random, the probability of such a small tree might be exceedingly low. The depth of the trees is cut-off, which can be modified with the -depth=n flag for some number n, and the predefined categories, Int in this case, are annoyingly restricted. Nonetheless, gr is a quick first pass at testing your grammar.

Listed in the repl, but not shown here, are (some of the) additional flags that gr command can take. The help command reveals other possible commands, included is the linearization, the l command. We use the pipe | to compose gf functions, and the -tr to trace the output of gr prior to being piped :

Arith> gr -tr | l
Add (Mul (Mul (EInt 999) (EInt 999)) (Add (EInt 999) (EInt 999))) (Add (Add (EInt 999) (EInt 999)) (Add (EInt 999) (EInt 999)))

the sum of the product of the product of 999 and 999 and the sum of 999 and 999 and the sum of the sum of 999 and 999 and the sum of 999 and 999

Clearly this expression is to too complex to say out loud and retain a semblance of meaning. Indeed, most grammatical sentences aren’t meaningful. Dealing with semantics in GF is advanced, and we won’t touch that here. Nonetheless, our grammar seems to be up and running.

Let’s try the sanity check referenced at the beginning of this post, namely, observe that \(linearize \circ parse\) preserves an AST, and vice versa, \(parse \circ linearize\) preserves a string. Parse is denoted p.

Arith> gr -tr | l -tr | p -tr | l
Add (EInt 999) (Mul (Add (EInt 999) (EInt 999)) (Add (EInt 999) (EInt 999)))

the sum of 999 and the product of the sum of 999 and 999 and the sum of 999 and 999

Add (EInt 999) (Mul (Add (EInt 999) (EInt 999)) (Add (EInt 999) (EInt 999)))

the sum of 999 and the product of the sum of 999 and 999 and the sum of 999 and 999

Phew, that’s a relief. Note that this is an unambiguous grammar, so when I said ‘preserves’, I only meant it up to some notion of relatedness. This relation is indeed equality for unambiguous grammars. Unambiguous grammars are degenerate cases, however, so I expect this is the last time you’ll see such tame behavior when the GF parser is involved. Now that all the main ingredients have been introduced, the reader

Exercises

Exercise 1.1 : Extend the Arith grammar with variables. Specifically, modify both Arith.gf and ArithEng1.gf arithmetic with two additional unique variables, x and y, such that the string product of x and y parses uniquely

Exercise 1.2 : Extend Exercise 1.1 with unary predicates, so that 3 is prime and x is odd parse. Then include binary predicates, so that 3 equals 3 parses.

Exercise 2 : Write concrete syntax in your favorite language, ArithFaveLang.gf

Exercise 3 : Write second English concrete syntax, ArithEng2.gf, that mimics how children learn arithmetic, i.e. “3 plus 4” and “5 times 5”. Observe the ambiguous parses in the gf shell. Substitute plus with +, times with *, and remedy the ambiguity with parentheses

Thought Experiment : Observe that parentheses are ugly and unnecessary: sophisticated folks use fixity conventions. How would one go about remedying the ugly parentheses, at either the abstract or concrete level? Try to do it!

Solutions

Exercise 1.1

This warm-up exercise is to get use to GF syntax. Add a new category Var for variables, two lexical variable names VarX and VarY, and a coercion function (which won’t show up on the linearization) from variables to expressions. We then augment the concrete syntax which is quite trivial.

-- Add the following between `{}` in `Arith.gf`
cat Var ; 
fun
  VExp : Var -> Exp ;
  VarX : Var ;
  VarY : Var ;
-- Add the following between `{}` in `ArithEng1.gf`
lincat Var = Str ;
lin
  VExp v = v ;
  VarX = "x" ;
  VarY = "y" ;

Exercise 1.2

This is a similar augmentation as was performed above.

-- Add the following between `{}` in `Arith.gf`
flags startcat = Prop ;

cat Prop ; 

fun
  Odd   : Exp -> Prop ;
  Prime : Exp -> Prop ;
  Equal : Exp -> Exp -> Prop ;
-- Add the following between `{}` in `ArithEng1.gf`
lincat Prop = Str ;
lin
  Odd e = e ++ "is odd";
  Prime e = e ++ "is prime";
  Equal e1 e2 = e1 ++ "equals" ++ e2 ;

The main point is to recognize that we also need to modify the startcat flag to Prop so that gr generates numeric predicates rather than just expressions. One may also use the category flag to generate trees of any expression gr -cat=Exp.

Exercise 2

Exercise 3

We simply change the strings that get linearized to what follows :

lin
  Add e1 e2 = e1 ++ "plus" ++ e2 ; 
  Mul e1 e2 = e1 ++ "times" ++ e2 ;

With these minor modifications in place, we make the follow observation in the GF shell, noting that for a given number of binary operators in an expression, we get the Catalan number of parses!

Arith> gr -tr | l -tr | p -tr | l
Add (Mul (VExp VarX) (Mul (EInt 999) (VExp VarX))) (EInt 999)

x times 999 times x plus 999

Add (Mul (VExp VarX) (Mul (EInt 999) (VExp VarX))) (EInt 999)
Add (Mul (Mul (VExp VarX) (EInt 999)) (VExp VarX)) (EInt 999)
Mul (VExp VarX) (Add (Mul (EInt 999) (VExp VarX)) (EInt 999))
Mul (VExp VarX) (Mul (EInt 999) (Add (VExp VarX) (EInt 999)))
Mul (Mul (VExp VarX) (EInt 999)) (Add (VExp VarX) (EInt 999))

x times 999 times x plus 999
x times 999 times x plus 999
x times 999 times x plus 999
x times 999 times x plus 999
x times 999 times x plus 999
Arith> gr -tr | l -tr | p -tr
Add (EInt 999) (Mul (VExp VarY) (Mul (EInt 999) (EInt 999)))

( 999 + ( y * ( 999 * 999 ) ) )

Add (EInt 999) (Mul (VExp VarY) (Mul (EInt 999) (EInt 999)))

Basic Extensions of Arith

Adding Variables

We can now

Parsing

Translation

Resource Grammar Library

Adding Swedish : ArithSwe.gf

Lists in GF

Embedding GF in Haskell

Appendix : Historical Developments

Prehistory :

CFGs, Chomsky Hierarchy, BNF

Natural Language Semantics & Martin Lof Type Theory :